Sunday, October 24, 2010

Does Religion Have a Universal Essence?

Both Geertz and Asad attempt to demonstrate how religion is integrated with and interacts with human culture. However, these scholars diverge on their specific understandings about how religion as a phenomenon is a part of human society. While their descriptions of religion are problematic, their work helps to demonstrate how a scholar’s assumptions can greatly affect how the relationship between the religious perspective and the secular perspective relate to one another.

Geertz believes that human beings communicate through symbols (The Interpretation of Cultures 89). Moreover, humans themselves construct cultural significance through the interpretation of groups of symbols (5). By extension, Geertz defines religion as “(1) a system of symbols which acts to (2) establish powerful, pervasive, and long-lasting moods and motivations in men by (3) formulating conceptions of a general order of existence and (4) clothing these conceptions with such an aura of factuality that (5) the moods and motivations seem uniquely realistic” (90). Implicit in Geertz’s definition is his assumption that religion is a discernible universal phenomenon, distinct from the non-religious sphere of culture.

Geertz elaborates further that humans rely upon symbols for epistemic purposes: “Man depends upon symbols and symbol systems with a dependence so great as to be decisive for his creatural viability and, as a result, his sensitivity to even the remotest indication that they may prove unable to cope with one or another aspect of experience raises within him the gravest sort of anxiety” (99). Hence, Geertz argues that symbols are central to the human’s process of learning, and that humans depend upon the symbols to be able to convey various epistemic significances.

Further evidence demonstrating Geertz’s assumption of an underlying religious paradigm, distinct from a non-religious paradigm is evident in his understanding that the religious perspective is merely one of several cultural perspectives. For instance, Geertz maintains that the common-sense perspective, which is distinct from the religious perspective, is common to all people (119). Furthermore, he argues that, typically, ritual action leads to an expansion of the practitioner’s common-sense paradigm (122). Thus, Geertz argues that religious belief can derive through religious ritual. This position, problematically, presumes a correspondence between ritual and belief.

Conversely, Asad argues that the pursuit of a definition of religion is misguided endeavour, and contends that formulating such a definition presumes that religion has a universal essence (Asad 252). Asad argues in a Foucaultian fashion that the development of religious traditions needs to be understood within the context of a history of a genealogy of knowledge. In particular, Asad examines the history of western Christianity, and demonstrates the importance of power for the transformation and growth of the tradition. Namely, Asad argues that “it is not mere religious symbols that implant true Christian dispositions, but power”, ranging from imperial, ecclesiastical, hellfire, church, fasting, and penance (242-243).

A second major contribution of Asad’s work is demonstrating that the western notion of separating the religious (private) and non-religious (public) spheres developed out of western Christian thought. Asad argues that Christianity redrew the boundaries between “the religious and the secular” several times during the medieval period (244), and, at a later period, “with the triumphant rise of modern science, modern production and the modern state, the Churches would also be clear about the need to distinguish ‘the religious’ from ‘the secular’, shifting, as they did so, the weight of religious truth more and more onto the moods and motivations of the believer” (244). Thus, Asad demonstrates that analyzing religion separate from the secular is a modern conception, and, therefore, it is harmful to impose such a distinction on all religious traditions since no such distinction may actually exist for the adherents. For instance, there would certainly be no such distinction among the Jews of the Second Temple period. Therefore, Geertz’s treatment of religion as a separate perspective from the aesthetic and scientific paradigms is rooted in the underlying assumption that there is a cultural distinction between the religious and the secular (250).

I appreciate Asad’s position that constructing a universal definition of religion might be a delimiting pursuit. However, neglecting the pursuit of such a definition renders our discussions about such traditions, which are typically considered religious, virtually meaningless. Without drawing reference to a definition of religion, we risk segregating cultural traditions such as Judaism, Christianity, and Islam, and treating them as if they are each distinct cultural phenomena with limited comparative value since each is an entirely unique phenomenon. A definition of religion (no matter how synthetic it might be) must be crafted and continually revised in order to advance our knowledge of these traditions. Though Asad is correct that attempting to define religion presumes a priori that there is an essence to the phenomenon; however, Asad’s call to altogether abandon the pursuit of such a definition likewise presumes that there is no essence to religion. Thus, perhaps a way to solve this anachronistic understanding of religion as a distinct paradigm from the secular would be to understand religion in a more general fashion.

Namely, drawing upon Geertz’s notion that common-sense is the most universal human paradigm, we might integrate religious tendencies into this most universal of human perspectives. Thus, common-sense should be extended to include the human disposition to reach beyond itself; for example, ‘where do the lightning bolts come from during a thunderstorm?’ ‘Who casts down these beams of fire/light to earth?’ The human urge to ask such questions should be considered fundamental to the human experience. Hence, under this more general paradigm, we can explain why both Hindus have traditionally attributed the rain to Indra, and many scientists have preferred to attribute the rain to natural meteorological phenomena. In other words, Geertz’s universal common-sense perspective should be extended to include the human desire to explain the unexplained. Thus, this revised common-sense perspective can be understood as the most universal human paradigm and can serve as a genus for the phenomenon of religion, and from which we might derive a definition of religion.

Sunday, October 17, 2010

Structure in Myth or the Myth of Structure?

Do human cultural traditions have any intrinsic meaning, or are our cultural institutions merely instances of a larger human chaos? This is one of the most important questions which both Lévi-Strauss and Foucault wish to address throughout their work. Lévi-Strauss argues that human myth is constrained by linguistic structures (213); on the other hand, Foucault, (apparently) conversely, seeks to demonstrate that institutions within society which appear to be governed by rational purpose must be understood as the inadvertent result of genealogical relationships, and ultimately the elite’s attempt to control deviancy (135-169).

Lévi-Strauss states “Mythology confronts the student with a situation which at first sight appears contradictory. On the one hand it would seem that in the course of a myth anything is likely to happen... But on the other hand, this apparent arbitrariness is belied by the astounding similarity between myths collected in widely different regions” (208). However, he argues that understanding myth as a language helps to alleviate these apparent contradictions (209). In order to discern this structure, Lévi-Strauss argues that the process of comparative mythology must be properly structured in the way that an orchestral score must be properly read in regards to the different instrumental parts which inevitably are included in the score (213). Furthermore, he argues that myths do not have “true” or “original” forms (217). Rather, a myth is a composite of all of its cultural variants; thus, a proper “structural analysis should take all of them into account” (217).

Clearly, Lévi-Strauss understands that to thoroughly analyze every permutation of a particular myth is impossible; hence, he attempts to strip several myths down to their basic components and structure them according to their most significant units (219). Lévi-Strauss’ rigid examination of these units leads him to describe families of myth where certain apparently key figures within a particular version might play especially significant roles but yet do not appear in cultural variants; for instance, consider his discussion on the Hopi myth of Shalako and the very different roles which the god Masauwu holds in certain variants of the tale, yet, in others, Masauwu may not even be present. In summary, Lévi-Strauss imposes a very rigid, almost mathematical, system upon the construction of mythology.

Foucault addresses the issue of structure from a decidedly very different perspective. Foucault begins by depicting two, apparently, very different types of penalties. Foucault historicizes the significance of the scaffold as important for public performances of bodily torture and execution, which served as a means of publicly displaying the disciplining of the perpetrator. Furthermore, the public display of the body following brutal forms of torture or execution would help to reinforce the severity of the penalty (34).

Following Foucault’s analysis of this earlier western system of public torture, he discusses the significance of the “gentle way of punishment”. However, Foucault does not believe that the shift between earlier forms of public torture and modern notions of imprisonment do not come about due to an informed ethical consciousness; instead, they are necessary to satisfy a demand for a universal mode of punishment for all perpetrators and crimes (116-117). Moreover, the goal of both the new gentle mode of punishment and its earlier more violent counterpart are the same, namely, to ultimately create a class which is obedient to the hierarchical elite. This is achieved by modern prisons through continual surveillance, which is experienced by the victim as “anonymous power”. Foucault states “this network [of constant surveillance] ‘holds’ the whole together and traverses it in its entirety with effects of power that derive from one another: supervisors, perpetually supervised” (176-177). Moreover, the institution of the prison fits into yet a greater system of coercion which includes military groups, medical facilities, schools, and religious institutions (300).

Thus, Foucault’s system initially appears to differ from Lévi-Strauss’. In particular, Lévi-Strauss has attempted to uncover the logical structure within human culture and, in particular, within myth, which are governed by certain universal human laws; in contrast, Foucault attempts to demonstrate that the presumption of purpose within human is merely accidental to a hierarchical political agenda. In other words, Lévi-Strauss demonstrates how despite the appearance of great diversity amongst myths (and more broadly human culture), the basic structures of myths are related; inversely, Foucault demonstrates that despite the appearance of particular logical structures within human society, social institutions need to be understood amidst a greater human genealogical relationship of thought. In this regard, Foucault might also understand himself as examining human mythology.

However, Foucault has also implicitly imposed a structure of his own upon the development of western penal traditions in regards to their genealogical development. In particular, Foucault has similarly demonstrated how the intellectual development of the prison came about through conformity to both a hierarchical human structure and an intellectual genealogy. In this manner, both Lévi-Strauss and Foucault share some sort of a notion of universal laws which guide human cultural developments.

Friday, September 17, 2010

How Should we Approach the Elephant in the Room?

There is a famous Indian parable about several blind men and an elephant. Each of the men attempts to touch a specific part of the elephant (such as the ears, the legs, the tail, etc.) in order to understand what it is. However, after touching the different parts of the elephant, they began to discuss the nature of what the animal was like and soon discovered that they vehemently disagreed about the elephant’s nature. This parable has been used for several different purposes within Jainism, Buddhism, Hinduism, and Islam such as to demonstrate the inexpressible quality of the universe. I argue that this parable might also be qualifiedly applied to religious studies scholars and their study of religion.

J. Z. Smith briefly outlines the evolution of the idea of “religion”; namely, he demonstrates how the concept is virtually a term fabricated by Christians which has expanded and contracted to include and exclude several cultural phenomena (such as Judaism, Buddhism, etc.) at different times. This, development of the term has lead Smith to conclude that “religion” is a synthetic term which scholars are free to define for their own purposes (“Religion, Religions, Religious” 281). In light of the cultural development of the idea of “religion”, this conclusion might appear sound. However, one must also account for the historical influx of information that gradually became available to the Christian scholars who defined the term. Thus, it is better to think about “religion” as a concept which has changed due to a growing body of information rather than Smith’s understanding that it is a term strictly defined by scholars’ ideological and political agendas.

Conversely, Smith is correct in identifying the roots of this concept as emerging out of a Christian world-view. Therefore, the idea of “religion” has often been susceptible to students’ incorrectly assuming that “religion” stems only from “belief”. Certainly, it was this Christian idea that “religion” stems from one’s belief that lead to Colonel Olcott’s (who was raised within the Presbyterian Christian tradition) assumption that authoring a Buddhist catechism would help to oppose Christian missionary endeavours within 19th century Sri Lanka (Lopez 29-34). Certainly, belief plays an important role within many cultural groups, but this is not true for several traditions typically identified as “religious”. Thus, it might be stated that one of the “blind men” or rather many Christian scholars identified the elephant or “religion” with belief; however, belief is, perhaps, not an intrinsic aspect to the phenomenon of “religion” as a whole.

This leads to the issue of classification. How should we classify ideas and concepts? In particular, how might we classify the elephant? Understanding ourselves and understanding institutions and concepts is intrinsically linked to how we understand the “other”. Similarly, “[p]erhaps the most fundamental classification of religions is “ours” and theirs,”” (Smith “Classification” 39). Unfortunately, while classification tends to be generalizing, it is indispensible within any academic discipline. In order to understand the unknown, should we not discuss how it is both like and unlike what is known? Learning comes out of utilizing cultural language and symbols which are already familiar to the learner to understand the unknown. Studying “religion”, therefore, must be done in the context of our own personal cultural backgrounds. Thus, if the blind man from the forest touches the leg of the elephant, he might say that the leg is strong and sturdy like a tree.

The same must be said of those who study “religion” and come from a confessional background (or from any and every background for that matter). Much of the study of religion has been separated into very specific fields such as the New Testament, or Rabbinics, etc. with little reference to the studies of the broader academy (Gill 974), just as the blind men examined different parts of the elephant without reference to other parts of the animal. Thus, a prolegomenon to resolving this issue would be through comparison and discussion of ideas within the broader field of religion. However, the method of comparative religions is not a new method within the study of religion, at least in terms of discussing similarities (969).

Therefore, what needs to be considered is if and how all of these distinctive cultural phenomena (Christianity, Judaism, Buddhism, etc.) relate to one another in regards to the human experience. Are religions related through shared common properties or do they have a family resemblance (Smith, “Classification” 36-37)? Conversely, are religions merely related synthetically due to a constructed and an expanding/contracting usage of the term “religion”?

I contend that the solution to these questions might come about through broader discussions and the “bridging-of-the-gaps” among the various subareas of religious studies. In the parable outlined above, the blind men are all touching the same thing, which, similarly, implies a commonality to the study of religion. Thus, we are all discussing a related phenomenon of “religion”, but what remains is for us to begin examining other parts of the elephant and discussing how these parts fit together into coherent whole. However, since the term “religion” basically developed out of a particular world-view (Christianity), it is up to religious studies scholars to integrate new world-perspectives and information into our developing understanding of “religion”, and, thereby, to change an originally external and mistaken term into a term which accurately describes this widespread human phenomenon.